By presenting and answering a range of popular opposing arguments, Gutting argues in "Did Zeus Exist?" that we do not, in fact, have any strong reason to assert with confidence that the ancient Greek god Zeus did not exist then, nor, indeed, that he does not now exist (2013).
Apart from the fact that it fits so neatly with our reading both of Law (2003) and of the subject matter of the chapter on cultural anthropology in Quest (Hartmann & Blass, 2007, pp. 3 - 43), I thought that Gutting's short essay is both fun and also raises some very important issues not only for cultural anthropology and the argument over whether or not any gods, demons, souls, ghosts, pixies, tooth fairies or similar things exist now, have ever existed or could ever exist, but also for academic work and critical thinking generally.
When Gutting presents a series of five opposing arguments to his thesis, that we have no sound grounds for asserting with certainty that Zeus did not once or does not now exist, he gives a great example of the importance of seriously addressing by first stating and then answering the strongest arguments against the main idea for which we are arguing. This is always something we need to be alert to: the support for our own idea is greatly strengthened if we present and show the weaknesses in the counter arguments against what we think. Correspondingly, if we cannot answer, or simply ignore, opposing arguments, our own thesis is greatly weakened since readers will reasonably assume we did not include and answer the opposing reasons for the very good reason that we could not answer them. And if we cannot answer objections, perhaps we should also be reassessing our own idea.
But I also think that Gutting, a very capable academic, knows exactly what he is doing and that he has been a bit naughty, as a few of his commentators on the article, which is actually a post in a blog that The New York Times hosts as a regular column, note: the same arguments apply to every god, ghost, demon, devil and other such supernatural entity that human beings have made up over the course of our history, and there are a lot of these: from the monotheistic religions of the despotic Middle-East, to the spirits, demons, ghosts, heavens, hells, souls and other strange entities of other types of religions. If it is true, as Gutting asserts, that the non-existence of Zeus cannot be absolutely asserted, any more than his actual existence, then so to is it equally impossible to assert that there is in fact any good reason to believe in Zeus, or any of the other wonderful beings and entities that populate the worlds religions past and present. It might well be true, but, as Gutting also points out, that is not evidence that can support a belief.
In fact, I think that Gutting's naughtiness goes a bit deeper: he must know that there is another strong argument in favour of asserting the non-existence of Zeus, past and present. But perhaps he left this as something to tantalise his readers as they first thought of it, and then realised that if true, it must also apply to every other such claim by the theistically or supernaturally minded. Can you think of it? A hint: it's something that Law discusses in the pages we have been reading over this pleasantly long weekend, and will hopefully get around to discussing in class tomorrow morning. But please feel free to share your ideas in advance in a comment, or two, or even three.
Should we really be open to the existence of Zeus? And Yahweh? And Jesus as god as well as man, and of Allah, and of souls, of devils, of demons, of vampires, of ghosts, or fortune telling, of spirit channelling, of reincarnation and the like?
And in case you can't access The New York Times article, I've also posted the text online here as a Google document, complete with the image.
__________
References
Hartmann, P. & Blass, L. (2007). Quest 3 Reading and Writing (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Law, S. (2003). Faith in the twenty-first century. In The Xmas Files: The philosophy of Christmas, (pp. 113 - 123). London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
I'm rather happy with my short, one sentence summary of Gutting's essay. Do you think I've done it justice?
ReplyDeleteAs we have been practising with exercise D. on page 18 of Quest (in my revised version), which we will definitely be looking at tomorrow morning, summarizing is an important academic reading and writing skill.
Now that I think about it a bit more, I'm not sure that vampires, at least some types of vampire, should be lumped in with the other things on my list of supernatural beings. At least some conceptions of vampires, perhaps the popular types in the 1994 film starring Brad Pitt and Tom Cruise, Interview with the Vampire, are not supernatural entities (Jordan, Geffen & Woolley). What do you think? I think we now need to have an argument about the meaning of the word supernatural, on which I welcome your ideas.
ReplyDeleteReference
Jordan, N. (director), Geffen, D. & Wolley, S. (producers). (1994) Interview with the Vampire: The Vampire Chronicles. United States: Warner Bros.
I loved the film, but I like Anne Rice's vampire novels even more. If you looking for some fun, light reading, I strongly recommend them. What character could be more cool than the vampire Lestat, who I am sure would be the first deny that he is anything supernatural. But perhaps he is wrong?
DeleteOn the other hand, I'm pretty sure that ghosts do belong on the list, along with Yahweh, Allah and souls, especially souls.
Rather awful grammar mistake there, but I think the meaning is clear. This is what comes of clicking "Publish" before you're proofread. But we don't expect perfection in response writing - and even the august New York Times has a column, After Deadline (another blog, actually) where their editors report on and analyse the grammar and vocabulary mistakes that their writers have recently made!
DeleteAnd in this post, "When Spell-Check Can’t Help", After Deadline looks at some spelling mistakes that The New York Times's writers missed, including the common confusion of the verbs affect and effect (Corbett, 2013).
DeleteReference
Corbett, P. B. (2013, June 4). When Spell-Check Can’t Help. The New York Times, After Dark. Retrieved from http://afterdeadline.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/06/04/when-spell-check-cant-help-19/
This rather wonderful example from the BBC News of exactly what Law discusses in the third part of the body of his essay makes for rather depressing reading: reliance for cures for HIV not on solidly supported science but on the Christian god (Strangwayes-Booth, 2013).
ReplyDeleteDepressing not simply because so many people continue to believe in gods of all sorts, along with magic, life after death (what could that even mean?), and the like, but because such faith in things that either do not exist or which have zero supporting evidence causes very real harm to the faithful believers and needless upset to those who care about them. I don't think it does society much good either.
In fact, as Law also suggests, in many cases, the support for old superstitions is not zero but lower, being actually negative. And still people believe! Perhaps human beings are genetically programmed by evolution to be this way?
But the nature of religions is something we'll be looking at more closely in Quest next week, when we come to the academic reading in Part 3.
References
Strangwayes-Booth, A. (2013, August 16). HIV patients told by Pentecostal pastors 'to rely on God'. BBC News UK. Retrieved August 18, 2013 from http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-23729684
Early morning coffee today - my weekend class at AUA starts at 8:00 AM. Happily, that means I'm free at 10:30, or thereabouts. But the early rise on Sunday is a killer.
Delete